Richard Shusterman Art and Religion


Pe³ny tekst wyk³adu wyg³oszonego przez prof. R. Shustermana w Oœrodku Badañ nad Pragmatyzmem w Krakowie 12 marca 2008
Full version of Prof. Richard Shusterman's lecture given at JDRC in Kraków, March 12, 2008

I.

Art emerged in ancient times from myth, magic, and religion, and it has long sustained its compelling power through its sacred aura. Like cultic objects of worship, artworks weave an entrancing spell over us. Though contrasted to ordinary real things, their vivid experiential power provides a heightened sense of the real and suggests deeper realities than those conveyed by common sense and science. While Hegel saw religion as superseding art in the evolution of Spirit toward higher forms that culminate in philosophical knowledge, subsequent artists of the nineteenth century instead saw art as superseding religion and even philosophy as the culmination of contemporary man’s spiritual quest. Artistic minds as different as Matthew Arnold, Oscar Wilde, and Stephan Mallarmé predicted that art would supplant traditional religion as the locus of the holy, of uplifting mystery and consoling meaning in our increasingly secular society dominated by what Wilde condemned as a dreary “worship of facts.”[1] By expressing “the mysterious sense . . . of existence, [art] endows our sojourn with authenticity and constitutes the sole spiritual task,” claims Mallarmé.[2] “More and more,” writes Arnold, “mankind will discover that we have to turn to poetry to interpret life for us, to console us, to sustain us. Without poetry, our science will appear incomplete; and most of what now passes with us for religion and philosophy will be replaced by poetry.”[3]

Such prophecies have largely been realized. In twentieth-century Western culture, artworks have become the closest thing we have to sacred texts, and art almost seems a form of religion with its prophetic breed of creative artists perennially purveying new gospels and its priestly class of interpretive critics who explain them to a devotional public. Despite wide recognition that art has an important commercial aspect, art sustains its cultural image as an essentially sanctified domain of higher spiritual values, beyond the realm of material life and praxis. Its adored relics (however profane they strive to be) are sacredly enshrined in temple-like museums that we dutifully visit for spiritual edification, just as religious devotees have long frequented churches, mosques, synagogues, and other shrines of worship.

In advocating a pragmatist aesthetics I have criticized this otherworldly religion of art because of the way it has been shaped by more than two centuries of modern philosophical ideology aimed at disempowering art by consigning it to an unreal, purposeless world of imagination. Such religion, I have argued, is the enemy of pragmatism’s quest to integrate art and life, a quest exemplified both in the classical Western notion of the art of living and some Asian artistic traditions, where art is less importantly the creation of objects than the process of refining the artist who creates and the audience who absorbs that creative expression.[4]

There is good reason, however, why this sacralization of art should remain so powerfully appealing despite the widespread recognition of art’s mercantile dimensions and worldly concerns. The reason, I believe, is that art expresses very deep meanings and spiritual insights that religion and philosophy once most powerfully provided but that they now no longer convey in a convincing way to most of today’s secular populations throughout the world. So, in this essay I would like to reconsider the art and religion nexus from a different angle. I wish to explore the idea that art provides a useful, even superior, substitute for religion, one that is free from the latter’s many disadvantages and that should be vigorously championed as an alternative that could eventually free our transcultural world from the hostile divisiveness and backward-looking attitudes that religions have inspired and instead lead us toward greater understanding, peace, and harmony.

But a contrary yet equally interesting hypothesis likewise demands consideration: that art cannot be separated from religion, that rather than a real alternative, art is simply another mode or expression of religion. Or, to put it in a provocatively suggestive paraphrase, art is simply the continuation of religion by other means. If this hypothesis has merit—indeed, even if there is simply some deeply indissoluble link between art and religion— then we cannot simply look progressively past religion toward art. For our philosophy of art will be seen to express the metaphysics and ideologies generated by a religious worldview, which thus indirectly (if not also directly) shapes our aesthetic philosophy, even if we are unaware of this religious influence or deny real credence to the religion in question. To make this point more concretely I will later take up two examples that show how different metaphysics of religion engender different philosophies of aesthetic experience and the relationship of art to life.

II.

Before turning our focus more narrowly to the spiritual promise and paths of religion and art, let me briefly dispose of philosophy. Through its modern professionalization and consequent desire to be scientific, philosophy has largely foregone the pursuit of the fuzzy realm of wisdom and emotionally tinged spirituality. It prefers, at least in its dominant form, to maintain the status of objective, rigorous knowledge explored through a cool attitude of critical analysis characterized by deadly “dryness” (as Iris Murdoch and others have so described it).[5] Though wisdom and spiritual feelings still find powerful expression in religion, its intimate connection with the supernatural and with dogmatic theological faith in truths about the world’s creation that have been decisively discredited by modern science has made religion an unconvincing option for most intellectuals in the West. Moreover, the long and appallingly painful history of religious discrimination, intolerance, persecution, and even crusades of vicious warfare makes it hard for many minds to embrace religion as their source of spiritual edification and salvation.

This should remind us of a further problem with religion in an ever more tightly knit and explosively globalized world. Religion (whose Latin etymology, religare, highlights the role of gathering, tying, and binding together) has long been recognized by sociologists as providing the essential glue of social unity in traditional societies. But there can be little doubt that its fractious pluralities and sects have also generated enormous division and disunity, combined with fanatical zealotry and intolerance that threaten to blow the world apart instead of bringing it together. The so-called clash of civilizations that is today so ominously trumpeted is largely a euphemism for a clash rooted in different religious outlooks, roughly that of the Judæo-Christian West and that of Islam, the last of the three great Abrahamic religions to emerge from the spiritually fertile Middle East. Even within the same religious civilization, region, and time, religion is just as likely to generate angry dissension as it is to insure harmonious cohesion. I witnessed such internal religious wars as a student in Jerusalem, where I was frequently reviled and stoned by fanatical orthodox Jews. But that is nothing in comparison to today’s tragic bloodshed between Suni and Shia Muslims in Iraq. Finally, the distinctly dour and ascetically demanding dimensions of most religions, with their strict and restrictive commandments often accompanied by dire threats of severe (even eternal) punishments for disobedience, can hardly attract contemporary sensibilities that seem much more inclined to open-minded freedom in the pursuit of happiness, including the pursuit of sensory pleasures.

Art, in contrast, seems to be free of these disadvantages, thus promising a more fruitful and satisfying way for the expression of wisdom and spiritual meaning, replete with abundant sensory, emotional, and intellectual pleasures. It provides the joys of mystery and myth without committing our faith to superstitions and thus inducing the bitter aftertaste of shame that our scientific conscience is likely to experience upon attempts to swallow discredited otherworldly beliefs. As Arnold therefore argues, art is where our intellectually evolving human race

will find an ever surer and surer stay. There is not a creed which is not shaken, not an accredited dogma which is not shown to be questionable, not a received tradition which does not threaten to dissolve. Our religion has materialised itself in the fact, in the supposed fact; it has attached its emotion to the fact, and now the fact is failing it. But for poetry the idea is everything . . . Poetry attaches its emotion to the idea; the idea is the fact. The strongest part of our religion to-day is its unconscious poetry.[6]

Not only poets but philosophers have similarly advocated art’s subsuming the role of religion. G. E. Moore, one of analytic philosophy’s founding fathers and the philosophical inspiration of the Bloomsbury aesthetic circle, wrote in 1902 that “Religion [is] merely a subdivision of Art” since “every valuable purpose which religion serves is also served by Art,” while “Art perhaps serves more” since “its range of good objects and emotions is wider.”[7] The idea that art provides a broader and more convincing alternative to religion has been reaffirmed in recent times by outspoken secular philosophers like the pragmatist Richard Rorty. In rejecting religion as a “conversation stopper,” Rorty champions the “inspirational value of great works of literature,” proclaiming “the hope for a religion of literature, in which works of the secular imagination replace Scripture as the principal source of inspiration and hope for each new generation.” This artistic religion he calls an “atheist’s religion.” Pluralistically liberal, it makes no claim to coerce behavior in the public sphere but only to console us individuals “in our aloneness” by connecting us with something far greater and inspiring beyond us—the marvelous world of great art—while guiding our efforts toward realizing both private perfection and more loving kindness to our fellow humans.[8]

If Rorty’s religion of art seems an overly private one, it is easy to find aesthetic thinkers who insist on art’s essential public role of social unity, including Rorty’s pragmatist hero (and mine), John Dewey. Describing art as “a remaking of the experience of the community in the direction of greater order and unity,” Dewey is even ready to suggest “that if one could control the songs of a nation, one need not care who made its laws.”[9] Art has long been celebrated for the unifying, harmonizing power of its communicative expression, which joins the most diverse audiences into a spellbound whole. Recall Friedrich Schiller’s praise that art through its pleasures of taste “brings harmony in society, because it fosters harmony in the individual.” “All other forms of perception divide man” by overly stressing either the sensuous or rational, while aesthetic perception harmoniously combines them. “All other forms of communication divide society” by appealing to differences, while art’s “aesthetic mode of communication unites society because it relates that which is common to all.”[10] Xunzi already made the same argument two thousand years earlier in China with respect to music (there construed to include also dance and poetic song): “When music is performed . . . the blood humour becomes harmonious and in equilibrium . . . The entire world is made tranquil and enjoys together beauty and goodness. . . . Thus music is the most perfect way to bring order to men . . . [because it] joins together what is common to all.”[11] And are we not witnessing an international art world where national and cultural borders are continuously being crossed in friendly exchanges of creative understanding rather than weapons of destruction?

Of course, we should also realize that the realm of art is not without its fractious divisions, fanaticisms, and intolerance. Besides the conflicts between proponents of elite and popular arts (that occasionally, as in the New York As-tor Square riots, have even erupted into real bloodshed), there is often fierce rivalry and bitter critique between different artistic styles—the schisms of “isms.” Such contention, however, rarely generates physical violence or cultural harm. In fact, one might argue that it provides a competitive spur to creativity. A more damaging and comprehensive, but sometimes less visible, form of art’s oppressive divisions is when the historically dominant concept of art disenfranchises the many forms of art that do not seem paradigmatic of that concept. From my Japanese colleagues I have learned that this is what happened in the Meiji period, when the Western conception of art was so coercively self-imposed on Japanese culture that its traditional arts (such as tea ceremony and calligraphy) were declassed from the category of art—geijutsu—and demoted to mere cultural practice, or what is called geidoh—literally ways of culture.[12] Clearly, in this case a particular hegemonic concept of art has done very painful cultural damage, which is now, fortunately, being rectified. But just as clearly the damages of artistic bigotry and enmity are infinitesimal when compared to the ravages wrought by religion.

There are many wonderful things about religion. Without its positive workings in the past, it is hard to believe that humankind would have developed the level of morality, rationality, love, community coherence, emotional richness, imaginative grandeur, and artistic creation that we have achieved. The argument for art replacing religion is that art sustains the valuable features of religion while minimizing or refining out the bad. John Dewey, for instance, who falls short of proposing art as a substitute for religion, nonetheless makes the argument that religion needs a process of purification through which its “ethical and ideal content” is separated from its unhealthy connection with belief in a “Supernatural Being” and with the often unsavory and outmoded ideologies, social practices, and ritual forms of worship that are simply the “irrelevant” accretion of “the conditions of social culture in which” the various traditional religions emerged. (For he recognizes that “there is no such thing as religion in the singular.”[13]) Dewey therefore recommends that we distinguish and preserve what he calls “the religious,” in contrast to religion in the concrete traditional sense. He defines the religious as an experience or attitude “having the force of bringing a better, deeper and enduring adjustment in life” that is “more outgoing, more ready and glad” than stoicism and “more active” than mere submission (CF 11-13). Moreover, in affirming that “any activity pursued in behalf of an ideal end against obstacles and in spite of threats of personal loss because of conviction of its general and enduring value is religious in quality” (CF 19), Dewey notes that the artist (along with other types of committed inquirers) displays such activity.

Indeed, in making his case for the religious as a commitment to the ideals and purposes of life, Dewey appeals to Santayana’s identification of the religious imagination with the artistic. “Religion and poetry,” writes Santayana, “are identical in essence, and differ merely in the way they are attached to practical affairs. Poetry is called religion when it intervenes in life, and religion, when it merely supervenes upon life, is seen to be nothing but poetry.[14] The conclusion that Dewey wants to draw from this, however, is that poetic imagination, with its “moral function . . . for . . . the ideals and purposes of life” (CF 13), should not be a mere playful, compartmentalized supervenience of art for art’s sake but rather a formative force in making social and public life, as well as private experience, more artistically beautiful and rewarding. In short, Dewey holds the pragmatist ideal that the highest art is the art of living with the goal of salvation in this world rather than the heaven of an afterlife.

III.

So far so good, we secular progressives would like to believe. But, in the questioning words of Shakespeare, “hath not this rose a canker?” Is art really so free of religion and those contingent societal ideologies and institutional practices that turn the ideal religious into objectionable religion? Could art have emerged and flourished, and could it continue to survive, without the beliefs, practices, and institutions of the cultures that gave birth to it and continue to sustain it, however contingent, imperfect, and questionable those impure societal dimensions of culture are? It is hard to see how it could, and how art could find meaningful content without these cultural beliefs, values, and practices deemed to be contingent, gratuitous, and impure. But even if it could exist in this purified ideal state, could art then be what Dewey desires—a formative influence for aesthetically reconstructing the world in better ways? How could it, if its imaginative ideals were not solidly connected with the webs of beliefs, practices, and institutions that structure society and thus are the necessary means for introducing positive changes to it? Dewey seems strangely unpragmatic here in advocating ideal ends while regarding the concrete cultural means—our institutional practices—as irrelevant.

If art is an emergent product of culture that cannot be meaningfully separated from it in the full-blown concrete sense of culture—including superstitions, silliness, prejudices, evils, and all—then one could make the following argument for art being essentially inseparable from religion. Art is indissolubly linked to culture. But culture, construed in the broad anthropological sense, is indissolubly linked to religion. In that important sense (influentially elaborated by Franz Boas and a host of other anthropologists and ethnographers) culture is “the system of shared beliefs, values, customs, behaviours, and artifacts that the members of society use to cope with their world and with one another, and that are transmitted from generation to generation through learning.”[15] In that sense, it would seem that throughout history “no culture has appeared or developed except together with a religion”; and, as T. S. Eliot further remarks, “according to the point of view of the observer, the culture will appear to be the product of the religion, or the religion the product of the culture.”[16] In more primitive societies, the different aspects of cultural or religious life are more intimately enmeshed so that they are hard to distinguish, and it is only through the process Max Weber describes as “rationalizing modernization” that what we now regard as the distinct fields of science, politics, religion, and art came to be conceived abstractly as separate from each other. But in reality, even in the modern, secular West, the separation cannot hold, as the manifold mixings and tumultuous frictions between these fields so often demonstrates. Consider the issue of abortion or stem cell research, or that of the public funding (or simply display) of religiously controversial art.

Now, if art is inseparable from culture, and culture is inseparable from religion, then it seems likely that art is also indissolubly linked to religion in a significant way. Certainly there is an essential and intimate historical linkage, as I mentioned at the outset. We would like to think that modern rationalization in the last two centuries has gradually severed the link. But history is not so easily undone in such short time, and perhaps our religious traditions, more than we think, remain vibrantly formative beneath the surface of the secular field of aesthetics and autonomous art—for instance, in our notions of artistic genius and creation, of art’s lofty spiritual values, of its elevation from worldly interests and mere real things, and in our models (and terms) for interpreting art’s mysteries. I cannot explore this question thoroughly in this short article, but let me make a start by considering one notion that has been rather influential in recent philosophy of art. Though repeatedly deployed by nonreligious philosophers of art in the analytic tradition, it seems hard to appreciate without taking seriously its religious meaning and aura. I refer to the notion of “transfiguration.”

Arthur Danto, the most influential of contemporary analytic aestheticians, has made the concept of transfiguration the keystone of his philosophy of art. An artwork may be an object visually identical with another quite ordinary thing that is not art. Therefore, Danto concludes that art requires the artist’s interpretation of the object as art (and that this interpretation must also be rendered possible by the state of art history and theory). Such interpretation is required to transfigure ordinary objects (what Danto calls “mere real things”) into works of art—which for Danto are things of an altogether different category and ontological status. Even before his famous 1981 book The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (whose influence has been so significant that the twenty-fifth anniversary of its publication was recently celebrated by the first online aesthetics conference), Danto deployed the idea of transfiguration to explain his crucial concept of the artworld, a concept that inspired the institutional theories of art that have also been very influential.[17] Already in his 1964 essay on “The Artworld” (where Danto defines the artworld as “stand[ing] to the real world . . . [as] the City of God stands to the Earthly City” [AT 582]), we find his key notion of transfiguration: that artworks are somehow transfigured into a higher, sacred, ontological realm wholly different from the real things of this world from which they may be visually or sensorily indiscernible or, as in readymades, with which they may even be physically identical. Already in this early essay we find Danto alluding to Warhol’s Brillo Boxes—his inspirational icon of miraculous artistic transfiguration—in terms of the Catholic mystery of transubstantiation, as symbolizing a whole world “of latent artworks waiting, like the bread and wine of reality, to be transfigured, through some dark mystery, into the indiscernible flesh and blood of the sacrament” (AT 580-81).

Though Danto describes his philosophy of art as inspired by Hegel, he distinguishes himself from Hegel in denying “that art has been superseded by philosophy” (AB 137). Indeed, in some ways he regards art as having taken over not only philosophy’s role of theorizing about art but also philosophy’s traditional concern with wisdom about life’s deep questions; for he insists: “Philosophy is simply hopeless in dealing with the large human issues” (AB 137). Danto, moreover, certainly concurs with the dominant modern trend to see art as superseding religion by conveying (in his words) “the kind of meaning that religion was capable of providing”: the highest spiritual truths and meanings, including the “supernatural meanings” of “metaphysics or theology.[18]

I have repeatedly pointed to Danto’s very Catholic religious rhetoric, but he always replies that he is a wholly secular person.[19] Though, as a student in Israel, I had first assumed that Danto was an aristocratic Italian Catholic transplanted to New York City, he later told me he was actually a non-observant Jew from Detroit, the son of a Jewish Freemason. All the Catholic rhetoric of transfiguration in his theory, he insists, does not reflect his personal religious beliefs but is merely a facon de parler, a manner of speaking. But does the religious dimension really disappear by calling it a mere manner of speaking? I don’t think so. First, manners of speaking cannot be easily separated from manners of living: real matters of belief, practice, and fact. Otherwise, those ways of speaking lose their efficacy. If the religious tenor of transfiguration did not still somehow resonate with our religious sensibility, with our religious experience, faith, or imagination (however displaced and disguised it may be), then this manner of speaking would not be as captivating and influential as it has proven to be.

This brings up a second point. Why did a secular Jewish philosopher choose this particular way of speaking about art, and why has it been so successful and influential? The reason, I think, is that the religious other-worldliness of the Christian tradition is deeply embedded in our Western artistic tradition itself and in the Western tradition of philosophy of art. It therefore has significantly shaped both of these traditions, even for artists, critics, and philosophers who do not consciously ascribe to Christian beliefs and attitudes. We should not think that we secular, or even anti-Christian, theorists of the Western artworld are entirely free of our culture’s religion in our theorizing; and in the globalized contemporary artworld shaped by the West, perhaps no one is completely free of it.

I am not claiming that art’s transfigurative power is a narrowly Christian idea. If there is anything that all our different cultures ascribe to art, it could be the transfigurative, transformative power of its creative expression and aesthetic experience. My key claim, rather, is that if we wish to understand art’s experience in terms of transfiguration, we should insist on recognizing at least two distinct underlying religious ontologies and ideologies of transfiguration, which I shall outline in the rest of this article. First, there is the dominant, familiarly Christian style of otherworldly elevation—based on a transcendental theology with an eternal, unchanging, disembodied God existing apart from the world he created (though miraculously embodying himself in his Son to save the human creatures of that world). Central to this theology is the corresponding notion of an immaterial, eternal human essence (the soul) that can be saved and elevated to God’s otherworldliness. In such religion of the transcendental gap, spirituality (be it in art or elsewhere) means an elevated distance from the ordinary material world, an ascent to a radically other world, whether the artworld or heaven. Here transfiguration typically implies a radical shift of metaphysical status, from the realm of mere spatiotemporal entities to a different, spiritually transcendent existence; so works of art must be distinguished (in Danto’s terms) from “mere real things.”

In contrast, Zen Buddhiststyle notions of art and religious practice offer a religion of immanence with no transcendental, personal God existing outside the world of creation; no eternal, personal, immaterial soul existing apart from its embodied manifestations; and no sacred world (an artworld or heaven) existing beyond the world of experienced flux. The essential distinction between the sacred and the profane (or between art and nonart) no longer marks a rigid ontological divide between radically different worlds of things but rather a difference of how the same world of things is perceived, experienced, and lived—whether artistically, with an inspiring spirit of presence and an absorbing sense of profound significance or sanctity, or instead as merely insignificant, routine banalities. Transfiguration, in such religions of immanence, does not entail a change of ontological status through elevation to a higher metaphysical realm but is rather a transformation of perception, meaning, use, and attitude. Not a matter of vertical transposition to an elevated ethereal realm, it is rather a vividness and immediacy of being in this world, of feeling the full power and life of its presence and rhythms, of seeing its objects with a wondrous clarity and freshness of vision. Consider this description of the path to transfigured insight provided by the Chinese Zen master Ch’ing Yuan of the Tang Dynasty: “Before I had studied Zen for thirty years, I saw mountains as mountains and waters as waters. When I arrived at a more intimate knowledge, I came to the point where I saw that mountains are not mountains, and waters are not waters. But now that I have got the very substance I am at rest. For it is just that I see mountains once again as mountains, and waters once again as waters.[20]

IV.

Let me now offer two concrete examples to illustrate these contrasting notions of artistic transfiguration. For the transcendental, classically Catholic notion, consider Raphael’s famous Transfiguration,[21] which depicts the episode related (with some minor variations) in the three gospels of Matthew, Mark, and Luke in which Jesus—taking along Peter, James, and John—goes up “into a high mountain apart by themselves.” There Jesus is visually transfigured before their eyes and then approached in conversation by (the long-dead prophets) Moses and Elijah, whose appearance affirms Jesus’s divine status as the Messiah. In coming down from the mountain, Jesus and his three disciples encounter the other disciples among a multitude in which a man cries out for Jesus’s help to cure his son from possession by an evil spirit, which Jesus’s disciples had not been able to exorcize. Raphael’s rendition of this episode includes both elements of the story—the miraculous transfiguration on the mountain and the distraught crowd with the demonically possessed boy down below. The canvas is divided vertically into two distinct parts depicting these two storylines. The mountaintop transfigurational scene understandably occupies the upper part of the picture, while the lower part portrays the agitated crowd before Jesus’s descent, with one red-robed figure (apparently a disciple) emphatically pointing up toward the mountain (and the picture’s center), thus pictorially linking with a dramatic diagonal the upper and lower parts of the canvas and their narrative elements.

Most significantly, for my argument, is that in the upper transfiguration scene, the figure of Christ is not simply elevated by being on the mountain top but actually hovers distinctly above it (and the prostrate accompanying disciples) in airborne levitation, flanked by but obviously higher than the two prophets who arrive to talk with him. His figure, moreover, is framed in a nimbus of bright light with just the hint of a golden aura around his head. The gospel of Matthew indeed asserts that when Jesus “was transfigured,” “his face did shine as the sun, and his raiment was white as the light.” But none of the Gospel versions describes Christ’s transfiguration as transcendental levitation above the mountain. Nonetheless, Raphael’s picture clearly depicts this, probably to highlight Christ’s heavenly, otherworldly essence and to suggest the essential otherworldliness of true spirituality, its indispensable transcendent movement beyond the world of ordinary real things.

Hegel deploys this painting to argue for art’s transfigurative elevation and capacity to sensuously convey the highest spiritual truths, even when they depart from the visual truth, since no normal view could, in truth, simultaneously include both the picture’s scenes. Yet Hegel writes, “Christ’s visible Transfiguration is precisely his elevation above the earth, and his departure from the Disciples, and this must be made visible too as a separation and a departure.”[22] If we go by the Gospel narratives, Raphael’s painting of the transfigured Jesus in complete “elevation” and “separation” from the earth lacks not only visual truth but also scriptural truth. But it wonderfully conveys the alleged truth of classical Christian transcendentalism (just as Hegel’s philosophical idealism does) while just as superbly implying its artistic analogue—that art’s transfiguration is an “elevation and separation” into some higher otherworldliness.

Moreover, through the implied narrative of Jesus’s success in curing by touch the demon-possessed boy after his disciples had failed to achieve this, the painting also conveys an artistic allegory about the divine transcendence of artistic genius. The hand of the great artist—someone like Raphael (whose very name in Hebrew means “God has healed”)—is analogically linked to the divine healing hand of Jesus himself, the Son of God. This analogy has enormous implications for our culture’s sharp divide between the heights of artistic genius and their lowly audiences, or between the high arts and the evil-possessed frenzy of the mass media arts of popular culture. But let me leave these issues of cultural politics aside so as to return to Hegel’s claim that this painting is a masterpiece through its communication of the spiritual truth of Christianity, even if it lacks, through its unrealistically divided canvas, objective visual truth.

Arthur Danto, in The Abuse of Beauty, defends Hegel’s view in using Raphael’s Transfiguration (which Danto finds great but not beautiful) to argue further that aesthetic visual qualities, including beauty, are never essential to artistic greatness. “Beauty is really as obvious as blue,” a simple perceptual matter grasped immediately “through the senses,” Danto claims, while art “belongs to thought” and therefore “requires discernment and critical intelligence” (AB 89, 92). He castigates a long tradition of theorists who think there is a kind of difficult beauty in art (or elsewhere) that is not a mere matter of immediate sensation but that requires the sort of “hard looking” that Roger Fry argued was necessary for seeing the beauty of Post-Impressionist paintings that were, on first impression, deemed hideous by the public. Rejecting the very idea of “deferred beauty that rewards hard looking” as a confusion of beauty and artistic insight, Danto scoffs at the thought that such looking could ever give us “the kind of sensuous thrill that beauty in the aesthetic sense causes in us without the benefit of argument or analysis” (AB 92-93).

While agreeing with Danto that beauty is not always essential to artistic success, I think there does exist beauty that is difficult to perceive but that is revealed through a kind of disciplined hard looking. Consider an example that also illustrates the Zen and pragmatist notion of immanent transfiguration I sketched above. My example derives neither from the official art world nor from the realm of natural beauty. It instead involves a large rusty iron barrel whose surprisingly wondrous beauty suddenly revealed itself to me after some sustained contemplative efforts during my own initiation into the disciplines of Zen during the year I spent in Japan doing research in somaesthetics.

Set on a hill near the coastal village of Tadanoumi on Japan’s beautiful Inland Sea, the Zen cloister Shorinkutzu where I lived and trained was directed by Roshi (Master) Inoue Kido. Roshi was liberal enough to take me on as a student (when he knew no English and my Japanese was very limited) and to recognize that the disposition of one’s kokoro (the heart-and-mind) is infinitely more important than having one’s legs tightly and enduringly entwined in a full lotus. Analogizing that rice plants could not be cut with a dull blade, he advised me to get up from my meditation cushion at the Zen-do whenever I felt tired and to go back to my sleeping hut for a nap to refresh and thus sharpen my mind. My powers of sustained concentration, he explained, would grow through enhanced mental acuity, not through merely stubborn efforts of willful endurance. However, in everything he thought important to the practice of Zen, Roshi was an effectively strict purist. A humane disciplinarian, Roshi did not spare the rod on his students when he thought it would instruct them. (I only avoided his instructive boxing of the ears because my Japanese was too poor to formulate a stupid question, though I once was severely reprimanded for leaving three grains of rice in my bowl.)

Near one of the two paths connecting the Zendo and the trainees’ sleeping quarters, I noticed a small clearing with an especially open and beautiful view of the sea, dotted with a few small islands of lush, soft, bushy green. In the clearing was a primitive stool, rudely constructed from a round section of log on whose short upright column (still adorned with bark) there rested a small rectangular wooden board to sit on and with no nails or adhesive other than gravity to fix it to the log. A couple of feet in front of the stool stood two old, rusty, cast-iron oil barrels (see Photo 1),[23] the kind I had often seen used as makeshift open-air stoves by homeless people in America’s poor inner-city neighborhoods. Readers more familiar with artworld usage might recognize them as the kind of barrels that Christo and Jeanne Claude painted and massively piled on their sides in two notable installations—Iron Curtain (Paris, 1962), and The Wall (Germany, 1999).[24] Sitting on the stool to look at the sea beneath the Dojo, one’s view was inescapably framed by the two corroding brownish barrels. I wondered why this ugly pair was left in such a lovely spot, spoiling the sublime natural seascape with an industrial eyesore.

One day I got the courage to ask Roshi whether I would be permitted to practice meditation for a short while in that spot overlooking the sea, though I dared not ask him why the hideous barrels (which the Japanese call “drum cans”) were allowed to pollute the aesthetic and natural purity of that perspective. Permission was readily granted, since Zen meditation can, in principle, be done anywhere, and Roshi felt I had progressed enough to practice outside the Zendo. I sat myself down on the stool and, having directed my gaze above the barrels, I fixed my contemplation on the beautiful sea while following Roshi’s meditation instructions of focusing attention on my breathing and trying to clear my mind of all thoughts. After about twenty

Photo 1. The drum cans of Shorinkutzu-Dojo.

minutes of effective meditation, I lost my grip of concentration and decided to end the session. Turning my glance toward the closest of the two barrels, my perception grew more penetrating and I found this object suddenly transfigured into a vision of breathtaking beauty—just as beautiful as the sea, indeed even more so. I felt I was really seeing that drum can for the first time, savoring the subtle sumptuousness of its coloring, the shades of orange, the tints of blue and green that highlighted its earthy browns. I thrilled to the richness of its irregular texture, its tissue of flaking and peeling crusts embellishing the hard iron shell—a symphony of soft and firm surfaces that suggested a delicious feuilleté.

Perhaps what seized and delighted me most of all was the beautiful fullness of its perceived presence. The rusty drum can had an immediate, robust, absolutely absorbing reality that made my vision of the sea pale in comparison. Rather than being transfigured into a transcendent world of immaterial spirituality, it transfiguratively radiated the gleam and spiritual energy with which the wondrous flow and flux of our immanent material world resonates and sparkles. Thus, I too felt transfigured, without feeling that either the barrels or I had changed ontological categories and levitated into transcendent ideality. Conversely, I realized that it was more the idea of the sea that I had been regarding as beautiful, not the sea itself, which I saw through a veil of familiar thoughts—its conventional romantic meanings and the wonderful personal associations it had for me, a Tel Aviv beach boy turned philosopher. The barrel, in contrast, was grasped as a beauty of the most concrete and captivating immediacy, but seeing that beauty required a sustained period of disciplined contemplation. Though the hard looking was initially not directed at the drum can, this alone was what enabled the perception of its beauty, and I could, on subsequent occasions, recover this vision of its beauty by foregoing the seascape and directing my absorbed contemplation at the barrels themselves.

The phenomenology of such hard looking, which I suspect is rather different from what Fry recommended for art, is too complex a matter to explore in this brief essay. Part of the complexity relates to distinctively Zen paradoxes of perception and being: my hard looking could also be understood as hard nonlooking since it was not motivated by a hermeneutic quest for the true meaning of the object, just as Zen thinking is often described as nonthinking and the fullness of its enlightenment as an emptiness. There is also the question of whether such immanent transfigurations should be most closely identified with the particular object in focus (the drum can), the experience of the perceiving subject, or the whole energized situation that shapes both of them and their encounter.

However we address these issues, one question must be faced forthwith: Were those transfigured drum cans art? Though clearly not part of the institutional artworld, they were just as obviously part of an installation work of deliberate design aimed at providing experiences that could be described as meaningful, thought-provoking, and aesthetically evocative.[25] And the deliberative design of this installation suggests that it was obviously “about something” (a condition of meaning generally deemed necessary for art). But what, exactly, the drum cans were about is a question that has many possible answers: the powers and possibilities of meditation, the surprising uses of industrial detritus, the contrast yet continuity of nature and artifact, the question of beauty (difficult and hidden versus easy and conventional), even the meaning I eventually found in it—the immanent transfiguration of ordinary objects that could make them art without taking them out of the real world and into a compartmentalized, transcendent artworld whose objects have an entirely different metaphysical status. Such immanent transfiguration, whose meaning of enriched presence is to fuse art and life rather than suggest their essential contrast and discontinuity, is where Zen converges with pragmatist aesthetics.

But what, then, becomes of works like Raphael’s Transfiguration? To recognize its religious meanings, must we insist exclusively on a transcendent metaphysics of art that separates art from real things and life? I do not see how this is any more necessary for understanding this work than zealously insisting that the Transfiguration episode with Jesus really happened and that its theological underpinnings are metaphysically true, thus excluding conflicting religious or scientific doctrines. I think I can appreciate to some extent the transcendent religious meanings of such works without sharing the relevant metaphysical and theological faith. But I suspect that a true believer could have a greater appreciation of the painting through such faith. I prefer to sacrifice that extra dividend of appreciation in order to maintain an ontology that is free of such supernatural otherworldliness and Christian theology, and an aesthetics that does not appeal to such other-worldliness to explain or justify art’s transfigurative power.

V.

Must we choose irrevocably between these two forms of transfiguration and their respective religious ideologies of art?[26] One reason for resisting this choice is that these options do not seem to exhaust the forms or interpretations of art’s transfigurative experience. I have not considered here the meaning of aesthetic transfiguration for the Confucian religious tradition, whose emphasis on aesthetic ritual and art over supernatural creeds have made it, for millennia, so attractive and influential for East Asian minds. It proved immensely more attractive than the religion of Mozi (an early rival of Confucius), whose more Christian doctrine of universal love came with the belief in a supreme supernatural deity (and lesser spirits and ghosts) but also with a bleak anti-aesthetic asceticism (that is dourly Protestant in character). Part of the genius of the ancient Confucians was to accept the growing force of the theological skepticism of their time by essentially eschewing supernatural religious metaphysics and confining their focus to the rescue and revitalization of the positive ideals and values embedded in traditional religious ritual and art. By expressing these ideals and values through more intellectually convincing interpretations that were focused on the aesthetic and ethical cultivation of both individual and society, Confucianism could thus offer an elaborately harmonious redemption of this-worldly life. Indeed, our own contemporary moment, with its growing skepticism in the supernatural and its pervasively aesthetic turn that tends to emphasize ostentation, richness, and complexity rather than Daoist or Zen simplicity, may make Confucianism the most appealing religion for the twenty-first century, at least for secular minds. I confess to be touched by its attractions, as I am touched by Zen and pragmatist meliorism.

But rather than trying to pick a winner here, I want to close by briefly raising another option since my survey of art’s religious traditions has been so sketchy and limited, neglecting the rich artistic traditions of other religious cultures such as Islam, Judaism, and the indigenous religions of Africa and America. Might we not adopt a more pluralistic approach to the religious ontology of art and perhaps let the context of the artwork and its cultural tradition determine for us which approach is best for appreciating its transfigurative meaning and spiritual truth? Can we be pluralist syncretists in our “religions” of art, even if we lack such flexibility in our traditional theologies, metaphysics, and religiously shaped ethics?

A pragmatist aesthetic pluralism would like to admit this possibility. If it were indeed possible, aesthetics could really be a wonderful bridge between cultures, even warring ones. But if aesthetics cannot be ultimately separated from a culture’s underlying religious attitudes, then it may not be feasible to realize this possibility in our imperfect world until we also work not only through but beyond aesthetics to transform our cultures and religious attitudes in the direction of deeper, more open-minded understanding. This does not mean a spineless, anything-goes tolerance of evident evil and flagrant falsehood. Nor should this involve the quest to abolish all real difference and the role of disharmony and dissent, without which we could never appreciate the agreeable harmonies of art.

NOTES

This essay was originally written and delivered as a plenary lecture for the 17th International Congress of Aesthetics, held in Ankara, Turkey, on July 9-13, 2007, and devoted to the theme of “Aesthetics Bridging Cultures.” I wish to thank Jale Erzen and the Congress Committee for inviting me, and I also thank the Congress participants for their helpful suggestions.

[1] Oscar Wilde, “The Decay of Lying,” in Complete Works of Oscar Wilde (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1994), 973.

[2] Stephan Mallarmé, Message Poétique du Symbolisme (Paris: Nizet, 1947), 2:321.

[3] Matthew Arnold, “The Study of Poetry,” in The Portable Matthew Arnold, ed. L. Trilling (New York: Viking, 1949), 300.

[4] I elaborate these pragmatist aims in considerable detail in Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living Beauty, Rethinking Art (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992; 2nd ed., New York: Row-man and Littlefield, 2000); Practicing Philosophy: Pragmatism and the Philosophical Life (New York: Routledge, 1997); Performing Live (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2000); and Surface and Depth (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2002).

[5] See Iris Murdoch, “Against Dryness” (1961), reprinted in Existentialists and Mystics (London: Chatto and Windus, 1997). Richard Rorty confirms this description of analytic philosophy’s desire to be “dryly scientific” in his “The Inspirational Value of Great Works of Literature,” in Achieving Our Country (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 129. Arthur Danto similarly describes contemporary philosophy (in the dominant analytic school he represents and favors) as professionally “cool” and remote from issues of wisdom; see his The Abuse of Beauty (Chicago: Open Court, 2003), xix; cf. 20-21, 137 (hereafter cited parenthetically in the text as AB).

[6] Arnold, “The Study of Poetry,” 299.

[7] G. E. Moore, “Art, Morals, and Religion,” an unpublished paper of 1902 cited in Tom Regan’s biographical study of Moore, entitled Bloomsbury’s Prophet (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1986).

[8] Richard Rorty, “Religion as Conversation Stopper,” in Philosophy and Social Hope (New York: Penguin, 1999), 118-24; Achieving Our Country, 125, 132, 136.

[9] John Dewey, Art as Experience (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), 87, 338; Freedom and Culture, in Later Works, vol. 13 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991), 70.

[10] J. C. F. von Schiller, Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man, trans. E. M. Wilkinson and L. A. Willoughby (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), 215.

[11] John Knoblock, trans., “Discourse on Music,” in Xunzi (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1980), 3:84.

[12] See Aoki Takao, “Futatsu no Gei no Michi [Two Species of Art]: Geidoh and Geijutsu,” Nihon no Bigaku [Aesthetics of Japan] 27 (1998): 114-27.

[13] John Dewey, A Common Faith (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), 3, 6-8 (hereafter cited parenthetically in the text as CF).

[14] Santayana’s remarks come from his Interpretations of Poetry and Religion (New York: Scribner, 1927). Dewey cites them in A Common Faith (13).

[15] D. G. Bates and F. Plog, Cultural Anthropology (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1990), 7.

[16] T. S. Eliot, Notes on the Definition of Culture (London: Faber, 1965), 15.

[17] Arthur Danto, “The Artworld,” Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964): 571-84 (hereafter cited parenthetically in the text as AT); and The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981) (hereafter cited parenthetically in the text as TC).

[18] Arthur Danto, After the End of Art (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997), 188; and The Madonna of the Future (New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux, 2000), 338.

[19] See, for example, our discussion at the Tate Britain, available at http://www.tate.org.uk/ onlineevents/webcasts/Arthur_danto/.

[20] It is interesting that Danto himself deploys this quotation in both “The Art-world” and The Transfiguration of the Commonplace.

[21] Images of this work are widely available on the Internet, including at http:// upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/5/51/Transfiguration_Raphael.jpg.

[22] G. W. F. Hegel, Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art by G. W. F. Hegel, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), 860.

[23] Or see http://www.fau.edu/humanitieschair/images/barrels.jpg for a color image.

[24] These images are available online, through the artists’ Web site, at http:// christojeanneclaude.net/fe.shtml and http://christojeanneclaude.net/gaso.shtml.

[25] I should mention that some artworld artists are similarly appreciative of the beauties of rust, deploying COR-TEN steel in their sculptures and installations because of its tendency to become rust-clad and thus potentially enhance their works’ aesthetic effect through rust’s subtle tones and textures. One striking example is Richard Serra’s marvelous Torqued Ellipses.

[26] A similar contrast might be discerned between different aesthetic interpretations of the notion of aura in different cultures that are shaped by different religious metaphysics. Walter Benjamin, for example, a secular Jew steeped in European culture (albeit much more engaged than Danto with his Jewish heritage), defines the aura in terms of “distance,” “uniqueness and permanence.” These features are, of course, connected with the idea of a transcendentally elevated sphere that is thus distant from ordinary reality and permanent because impervious (through its divinity) to change. Moreover, connection with the distantly elevated divinity of monotheism makes the notion of aura (in artistic authenticity as well as in the case of true divinity) a matter also of uniqueness, even in the mysterious unity of the divine trinity of the Christian godhead or the plural instances of authentic prints or sculptures that come from the same block or cast. See Walter Benjamin, “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction,” in Illuminations (New York: Schocken, 1968), 222-23. In contrast, the aura of Zen aesthetic experiences highlights impermanence and the proximity of the everyday and the common; hence, reproducibility here does not have to destroy the aura.

 

top